Math 2710

Sep 2-6

Some catch-up from prior classes

Two notes

Definitions

Although I never said this explicitly, a definition is an ‘if and only if’ statment. When I write:

Definition: An integer \(x\) is “5-ish” if there is an integer \(n\) so that \(x=5n\)

I am actually saying that "\(x\) is 5-ish IF AND ONLY IF there is an integer \(n\) so that \(x=5n\).

Negation of implication

The easiest way to express NOT (A implies B) is as (A and NOT B). Check the truth tables.

1.4 Variable statements and quantifiers

First examples

Compare the following three statements

All make assertions about the set \(U\) of UConn students

Universal quantifier (For all, for every, for each)

A statement that includes a universal quantifier makes a claim about ALL objects of a particular type.

Symbolic Form

Existential quantifier (There is, there exists, for some)

Symbolic Form

Relation between universal and existential quantifiers

To show that the statement Every UConn student has watched every minute of Game of Thrones is FALSE, you must produce an example of a UConn student who has NOT watched every minute. So the negation of this claim is:

Some UConn student has not watched every minute of Game of Thrones or There is a UConn student who has not watched every minute of Game of Thrones

To show that the statement There is a UConn student who has watched every minute of Game of Thrones is FALSE, you must show that: No student has watched every minute of Game of Thrones or All students at UConn have NOT watched every minute of Game of Thrones.

Symbolic Form (page 11 of the text)

Examples

The statement \((S\cap T)\subset U\) is the statement that

\(\forall x, ((x\in S) and (x\in T)) \implies x\in U\)

Write the negation of this statement in a simple form.

Second order statements

Second order statements have two quantifiers.

For all \(x\), there exists \(y\).

There exists \(y\), so that for all \(x\)

An example

Definition: Given two integers \(n\) and \(d\), we say that

-\(n\) is divisible by \(d\)

or

-\(n\) is a multiple of \(d\)

or

-\(d\) divides \(n\)

if there exists an integer \(m\) so that \(n=dm\).

Divisibility examples

A. Let \(X=\{ n\in \mathbb{Z}: 3|n \}\) and let \(Y=\{n\in \mathbb{Z}: 5|n\}\). Show that \(X\cap Y=\{n\in \mathbb{Z}: 15|n\}\).

B. Let \(X=\{n \in \mathbb{Z}: 6|n\}\) and let \(Y=\{n \in \mathbb{Z}: 4|n\}\). Show that \(X\cap Y\) is not equal to \(W=\{n\in\mathbb{Z}: 24|z\}\).

Section 1.5: Proofs

Main ingredients

Remember that a mathematical proof is a careful explanation of the logical reasons for the truth of a proposition. Good proofs are:

-rigorous, meaning that they present a completely, logically correct argument -informative, meaning that they convey the reasoning behind the truth of the proposition being proved -efficient, meaning that they are as short as possible while still being rigorous and informative.

Things to try

Faced with a proposition to be provided:

Examples 1: Direct Implication

Proposition: Let \(S\) and \(T\) be sets. Prove that if \(S \cap T=S\) then \(S\subset T\).

Analysis: This is a direct implication \(P\implies Q\).

\(S\cap T = S\) means that \(x\in S \mathrm{\ and\ }x\in T\) if and only if \(x\in S\).

\(S\subset T\) means that \((x\in S)\implies (x\in T)\).

Look at the truth tables and compare with paragraph on page 14.

Examples 2: If and only if

Proposition: \(S \cap T = S\cup T\) if and only if \(S=T\).

Look at truth tables and compare with paragraph on page 14.

Examples 3: Contrapositive

Proposition: If \(x\) is a real number such that \(x^3+7x^2<9\) then \(x<1.1\).

\(P\implies Q\) is equivalent to \(\sim Q \implies \sim P\).

Must show: \(x\ge 1.1\) implies \(x^3+7x^2\ge 9\).

Example 4: Contradiction.

Proposition: There is no largest integer.

Suppose that this statement \(P\) is false. Then there is a largest integer; call it \(n\). Since \(n\) is the largest integer, \(n+1\) must be less than or equal to \(n\). Therefore \(n+1\le n\) or \(1\le 0\). This is false.

Let \(Q\) be the statement “There is no largest integer.” Let \(P\) be the statement \(1\le 0\).

Then we have shown that \(~Q \implies P\). Since \(P\) is false, this implication can only be true if \(~Q\) is false, so \(Q\) is true.

This is called PROOF BY CONTRADICTION.

Example 5: Compound implications

Proposition: If \(x\) is a real number, then \((x-a)(x-b)=0\) if and only if either \(x=a\) or \(x=b\).

Here \(P\) is \((x-a)(x-b)=0\). The conclusion is of the form \(Q \mathrm{\ or\ } R\) where \(Q\) is \(x=a\) and \(R\) is \(x=b\).

One approach: \(P\implies (Q\mathrm{\ or\ } R)\) is equivalent to \(P\mathrm{\ and\ }~R\implies Q\). So \((x-a)(x-b)=0\) and \(x\not=a\) means we can divide by \(x-a\) to get \(x=b\).

In the other direction, try each possibility.

Discussion Problems

Selected problems from 55-61 on page 21 and 65-70 on page 22 of the book.